Chapter 1. Modes of holding and apprehending
Propositions
§ 1. Modes of
holding Propositions
{3} 1. PROPOSITIONS (consisting of a subject and predicate united
by the copula) may take a categorical, conditional, or interrogative
form.
(1) An interrogative, when they ask a Question, (e.g. Does
Free-trade benefit the poorer classes?) and imply the possibility of
an affirmative or negative resolution of it.
(2) A conditional, when they express a Conclusion (e.g. Free-trade
therefore benefits the poorer classes), and at once imply, and imply
their dependence on, other propositions.
(3) A categorical, when they simply make an Assertion (e.g.
Free-trade does benefit), and imply the absence of any condition or
reservation of any kind, looking neither before nor behind, as resting
in themselves and being intrinsically complete.
These three modes of shaping a proposition, distinct as they are
from each other, follow each other in natural sequence. A proposition,
which starts with being a {4} Question, may become a Conclusion, and
then be changed into an Assertion; but it has of course ceased to be a
question, so far forth as it has become a conclusion, and has rid
itself of its argumentative form—that is, has ceased to be a
conclusion,—so far forth as it has become an assertion. A question
has not yet got so far as to be a conclusion, though it is the
necessary preliminary of a conclusion; and an assertion has got beyond
being a mere conclusion, though it is the natural issue of a
conclusion. Their correlation is the measure of their distinction one
from another.
No one is likely to deny that a question is distinct both from a
conclusion and from an assertion; and an assertion will be found to be
equally distinct from a conclusion. For, if we rest our affirmation on
arguments, this shows that we are not asserting; and, when we assert,
we do not argue. An assertion is as distinct from a conclusion, as a
word of command is from a persuasion or recommendation. Command and
assertion, as such, both of them, in their different ways, dispense
with, discard, ignore, antecedents of any kind, though antecedents may
have been a sine quâ non condition of their being elicited.
They both carry with them the pretension of being personal acts.
In insisting on the intrinsic distinctness of these three modes of
putting a proposition, I am not maintaining that they may not co-exist
as regards one and the same subject. For what we have already
concluded, we may, if we will, make a question of; and what we are
asserting, we may of course conclude over again. We may assert, to one
man, and conclude to another, {5} and ask of a third; still when we
assert, we do not conclude, and, when we assert or conclude, we do not
question.
2. The internal act of holding propositions is for the most part
analogous to the external act of enunciating them; as there are three
ways of enunciating, so are there three ways of holding them, each
corresponding to each. These three mental acts are Doubt, Inference,
and Assent. A question is the expression of a doubt; a conclusion is
the expression of an act of inference; and an assertion is the
expression of an act of assent. To doubt, for instance, is not to see
one's way to hold, that Free-trade is or that it is not a benefit; to
infer, is to hold on sufficient grounds that Free-trade may, must, or
should be a benefit; to assent to the proposition, is to hold that
Free-trade is a benefit.
Moreover, propositions, while they are the material of these three
enunciations, are also the objects of the three corresponding mental
acts; and as without a proposition there cannot be a question,
conclusion, or assertion, so without a proposition there is nothing to
doubt about, nothing to infer, nothing to assent to. Mental acts of
whatever kind presuppose their objects.
And, since the three enunciations are distinct from each other,
therefore the three mental acts also, Doubt, Inference, and Assent,
are, with reference to one and the same proposition, distinct from
each other; else, why should their several enunciations be distinct?
And indeed it is very evident, that, so far forth as we infer, we do
not doubt, and that, when we assent, {6} we are not inferring, and,
when we doubt, we cannot assent.
And in fact, these three modes of entertaining propositions,—doubting
them, inferring them, assenting to them, are so distinct in their
action, that, when they are severally carried out into the
intellectual habits of an individual, they become the principles and
notes of three distinct states or characters of mind. For instance, in
the case of Revealed Religion, according as one or other of these is
paramount within him, a man is a sceptic as regards it; or a
philosopher, thinking it more or less probable considered as a
conclusion of reason; or he has an unhesitating faith in it, and is
recognized as a believer. If he simply disbelieves, or dissents, then
he is assenting to the contradictory of the thesis, viz. to the
proposition that there is no Revelation.
Many minds of course there are, which are not under the predominant
influence of any one of the three. Thus men are to be found of
irreflective, impulsive, unsettled, or again of acute minds, who do
not know what they believe and what they do not, and who may be by
turns sceptics, inquirers, or believers; who doubt, assent, infer, and
doubt again, according to the circumstances of the season. Nay
further, in all minds there is a certain coexistence of these distinct
acts; that is, of two of them, for we can at once infer and assent,
though we cannot at once either assent or infer and also doubt.
Indeed, in a multitude of cases we infer truths, or apparent truths,
before, and while, and after we assent to them.
Lastly, it cannot be denied that these three acts are all natural
to the mind; I mean, that, in exercising {7} them, we are not
violating the laws of our nature, as if they were in themselves an
extravagance or weakness, but are acting according to it, according to
its legitimate constitution. Undoubtedly, it is possible, it is
common, in the particular case, to err in the exercise of Doubt, of
Inference, and of Assent; that is, we may be withholding a judgment
about propositions on which we have the means of coming to some
definite conclusion; or we may be assenting to propositions which we
ought to receive only on the credit of their premisses, or again to
keep ourselves in suspense about; but such errors of the individual
belong to the individual, not to his nature, and cannot avail to
forfeit for him his natural right, under proper circumstances, to
doubt, or to infer, or to assent. We do but fulfil our nature in
doubting, inferring, and assenting; and our duty is, not to abstain
from the exercise of any function of our nature, but to do what is in
itself right rightly.
3. So far in general:—in this Essay I treat of propositions only
in their bearing upon concrete matter, and I am mainly concerned with
Assent; with Inference, in its relation to Assent, and only such
inference as is not demonstration; with Doubt hardly at all. I dismiss
Doubt with one observation. I have here spoken of it simply as a
suspense of mind, in which sense of the word, to have "no
doubt" about a thesis is equivalent to one or other of the two
remaining acts, either to inferring it or else assenting to it.
However, the word is often taken to mean the deliberate recognition of
a thesis as being uncertain; in this sense Doubt is nothing {8} else
than an assent, viz. an assent to a proposition at variance with the
thesis, as I have already noticed in the case of Disbelief.
Confining myself to the subject of Assent and Inference, I observe
two points of contrast between them.
The first I have already noted. Assent is unconditional; else, it
is not really represented by assertion. Inference is conditional,
because a conclusion at least implies the assumption of premisses, and
still more, because in concrete matter, on which I am engaged,
demonstration is impossible.
The second has regard to the apprehension necessary for holding a
proposition. We cannot assent to a proposition, without some
intelligent apprehension of it; whereas we need not understand it at
all in order to infer it. We cannot give our assent to the proposition
that "x is z," till we are told something about one or other
of the terms; but we can infer, if "x is y, and y is z, that x is
z," whether we know the meaning of x and z or no.
These points of contrast and their results will come before us in
due course: here, for a time leaving the consideration of the modes of
holding propositions, I proceed to inquire into what is to be
understood by apprehending them. {9}
Top | Contents | Works
| Home
§ 2. Modes of
apprehending Propositions
BY our apprehension of propositions I mean our imposition of a
sense on the terms of which they are composed. Now what do the terms
of a proposition, the subject and predicate, stand for? Sometimes they
stand for certain ideas existing in our own minds, and for nothing
outside of them; sometimes for things simply external to us, brought
home to us through the experiences and informations we have of them.
All things in the exterior world are unit and individual, and are
nothing else; but the mind not only contemplates those unit realities,
as they exist, but has the gift, by an act of creation, of bringing
before it abstractions and generalizations, which have no existence,
no counterpart, out of it.
Now there are propositions, in which one or both of the terms are
common nouns, as standing for what is abstract, general, and
non-existing, such as "Man is an animal, some men are learned, an
Apostle is a creation of Christianity, a line is length without
breadth, to err is human, to forgive divine." These I shall call
notional propositions, and the apprehension with which we infer or
assent to them, notional.
And there are other propositions, which are composed of singular
nouns, and of which the terms stand for {10} things external to us,
unit and individual, as "Philip was the father of
Alexander," "the earth goes round the sun," "the
Apostles first preached to the Jews;" and these I shall call real
propositions, and their apprehension real.
There are then two kinds of apprehension or interpretation to which
propositions may be subjected, notional and real.
Next I observe, that the same proposition may admit of both of
these interpretations at once, having a notional sense as used by one
man, and a real as used by another. Thus a schoolboy may perfectly
apprehend, and construe with spirit, the poet's words, "Dum
Capitolium scandet cum tacitâ Virgine Pontifex;" he has seen
steep hills, flights of steps, and processions; he knows what enforced
silence is; also he knows all about the Pontifex Maximus, and the
Vestal Virgins; he has an abstract hold upon every word of the
description, yet without the words therefore bringing before him at
all the living image which they would light up in the mind of a
contemporary of the poet, who had seen the fact described, or of a
modern historian who had duly informed himself in the religious
phenomena, and by meditation had realized the Roman ceremonial, of the
age of Augustus. Again, "Dulce et decorum est pro patriâ mori,"
is a mere common-place, a terse expression of abstractions in the mind
of the poet himself, if Philippi is to be the index of his patriotism,
whereas it would be the record of experiences, a sovereign dogma, a
grand aspiration, inflaming the imagination, piercing the heart, of a
Wallace or a Tell. {11}
As the multitude of common nouns have originally been singular, it
is not surprising that many of them should so remain still in the
apprehension of particular individuals. In the proposition "Sugar
is sweet," the predicate is a common noun as used by those who
have compared sugar in their thoughts with honey or glycerine; but it
may be the only distinctively sweet thing in the experience of a
child, and may be used by him as a noun singular. The first time that
he tastes sugar, if his nurse says, "Sugar is sweet" in a
notional sense, meaning by sugar, lump-sugar, powdered, brown, and
candied, and by sweet, a specific flavour or scent which is found in
many articles of food and many flowers, he may answer in a real sense,
and in an individual proposition "Sugar is sweet," meaning
"this sugar is this sweet thing."
Thirdly, in the same mind and at the same time, the same
proposition may express both what is notional and what is real. When a
lecturer in mechanics or chemistry shows to his class by experiment
some physical fact, he and his hearers at once enunciate it as an
individual thing before their eyes, and also as generalized by their
minds into a law of nature. When Virgil says, "Varium et mutabile
semper fœmina," he both sets before his readers what he means to
be a general truth, and at the same time applies it individually to
the instance of Dido. He expresses at once a notion and a fact.
Of these two modes of apprehending propositions, notional and real,
real is the stronger; I mean by stronger the more vivid and forcible.
It is so to be accounted for the very reason that it is concerned with
{12} what is either real or is taken for real; for intellectual ideas
cannot compete in effectiveness with the experience of concrete facts.
Various proverbs and maxims sanction me in so speaking, such as,
"Facts are stubborn things," "Experientia docet,"
"Seeing is believing;" and the popular contrast between
theory and practice, reason and sight, philosophy and faith. Not that
real apprehension, as such, impels to action, any more than notional;
but it excites and stimulates the affections and passions, by bringing
facts home to them as motive causes. Thus it indirectly brings about
what the apprehension of large principles, of general laws, or of
moral obligations, never could effect.
Reverting to the two modes of holding propositions, conditional and
unconditional, which was the subject of the former Section, that is,
inferences and assents, I observe that inferences, which are
conditional acts, are especially cognate to notional apprehension, and
assents, which are unconditional, to real. This distinction, too, will
come before us in the course of the following chapters.
And now I have stated the main subjects of which I propose to
treat; viz. the distinctions in the use of propositions, which I have
been drawing out, and the questions which those distinctions involve.
Top | Contents | Works
| Home
Newman Reader Works of John Henry Newman
Copyright © 2007 by The National Institute for Newman Studies. All rights reserved.
|